Cf: Peirce’s 1870 “Logic of Relatives” • Comment 11.20
https://inquiryintoinquiry.com/2014/06/01/peirces-1870-logic-of-relatives-c…
Peirce’s 1870 “Logic of Relatives” • Comment 11.20
https://oeis.org/wiki/Peirce%27s_1870_Logic_Of_Relatives_%E2%80%A2_Part_2#C…
All,
We come to the last of Peirce’s statements about the “number of” function,
first quoted in Selection 11 and again with the whole set in Comment 11.2.
https://inquiryintoinquiry.com/2014/04/29/peirces-1870-logic-of-relatives-s…
https://inquiryintoinquiry.com/2014/04/30/peirces-1870-logic-of-relatives-c…
NOF 4.1
=======
<QUOTE CSP:>
The conception of multiplication we have adopted is
that of the application of one relation to another. […]
Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea,
for 2 × 3 is a pair of triplets, and 3 × 2 is a triplet of pairs,
where “triplet of” and “pair of” are evidently relatives.
If we have an equation of the form
• xy = z
and there are just as many x’s per y as there are, per things,
things of the universe, then we have also the arithmetical equation,
• [x][y] = [z].
(Peirce, CP 3.76)
</QUOTE>
Peirce here observes what may be called a “contingent morphism”.
On a condition he gives, the mapping of logical terms to their
corresponding numbers preserves the multiplication of relative
terms after the fashion of the following formula.
• v(xy) = v(x) v(y).
Equivalently:
• [xy] = [x][y].
The condition for this to hold is expressed by Peirce in the following manner.
“There are just as many x’s per y as there are, per things, things of the universe.”
Peirce’s phrasing on this point is admittedly hard to parse but I think
if we stick with his story to the end we can see what he is driving at.
NOF 4.2
=======
<QUOTE CSP:>
For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to
a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then
• [t][f] = [tf]
holds arithmetically. (Peirce, CP 3.76).
</QUOTE>
Now that is something we can sink our teeth into and trace the
bigraph representation of the situation. It will help to recall
our first examination of the “tooth of” relation and to adjust the
picture we sketched of it on that occasion.
Transcribing Peirce’s example:
Let m = man
and t = tooth of___.
Then v(t) = [t] = [tm]/[m].
That is to say, the number of the relative term “tooth of”
is equal to the number of teeth of humans divided by the
number of humans. In a universe of perfect human dentition
this gives a quotient of 32.
The dyadic relative term t determines a dyadic relation T ⊆ X × Y,
where X contains all the teeth and Y contains all the people under
discussion.
To make the case as simple as possible and still cover the point,
suppose there are just four people in our universe of discourse
and just two of them are French. The bigraph product below
shows the pertinent facts of the case.
Figure 52. Bigraph Product T ◦ F
https://inquiryintoinquiry.files.wordpress.com/2022/03/lor-1870-bigraph-pro…
In this picture the order of relational composition flows down the page.
For convenience in composing relations, the absolute term f = Frenchman
is inflected by the comma functor to form the dyadic relative term
f, = Frenchman that is___, which in turn determines the idempotent
representation of Frenchmen as a subset of mankind, F ⊆ Y × Y.
Now let’s see if we can use this picture
to make sense of the following statement.
NOF 4.2
=======
<QUOTE CSP:>
For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to
a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then
• [t][f] = [tf]
holds arithmetically. (Peirce, CP 3.76).
</QUOTE>
In statistical terms, Peirce is saying this: If the population of
Frenchmen is a *fair sample* of the general population with regard
to the factor of dentition, then the morphic equation,
• [tf] = [t][f],
whose transpose gives the equation,
• [t] = [tf]/[f],
is every bit as true as the defining equation in this circumstance, namely,
• [t] = [tm]/[m].
Regards,
Jon