Precursors Of Category Theory • 2
•
https://inquiryintoinquiry.com/2024/05/26/precursors-of-category-theory-2-a/
❝Thanks to art, instead of seeing one world only, our own, we see
that world multiply itself and we have at our disposal as many
worlds as there are original artists …❞
— Marcel Proust
All,
When it comes to looking for the continuities of the category concept
across different systems and systematizers, we don't expect to find
their kinship in the names or numbers of categories, since those are
legion and their divisions deployed on widely different planes of
abstraction, but in their common function.
Aristotle —
❝Things are equivocally named, when they have the name only in common,
the definition (or statement of essence) corresponding with the name
being different. For instance, while a man and a portrait can properly
both be called animals (ζωον), these are equivocally named. For they
have the name only in common, the definitions (or statements of essence)
corresponding with the name being different. For if you are asked to
define what the being an animal means in the case of the man and the
portrait, you give in either case a definition appropriate to that
case alone.
❝Things are univocally named, when not only they bear the same name
but the name means the same in each case — has the same definition
corresponding. Thus a man and an ox are called animals. The name
is the same in both cases; so also the statement of essence. For
if you are asked what is meant by their both of them being called
animals, you give that particular name in both cases the same
definition.❞ (Aristotle, Categories, 1.1a1–12).
Translator's Note. ❝Ζωον in Greek had two meanings, that is
to say, living creature, and, secondly, a figure or image in
painting, embroidery, sculpture. We have no ambiguous noun.
However, we use the word ‘living’ of portraits to mean ‘true
to life’.❞
In the logic of Aristotle categories are adjuncts to reasoning whose
function is to resolve ambiguities and thus to prepare equivocal signs,
otherwise recalcitrant to being ruled by logic, for the application of
logical laws. The example of ζωον illustrates the fact that we don't
need categories to “make” generalizations so much as to “control”
generalizations, to reign in abstractions and analogies which have
been stretched too far.
References —
• Aristotle, “The Categories”, Harold P. Cooke (trans.), pp. 1–109
in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann,
London, UK, 1938.
• Karpeles, Eric (2008), Paintings in Proust, Thames and Hudson,
London, UK.
Resources —
Precursors Of Category Theory
•
https://oeis.org/wiki/Precursors_Of_Category_Theory
Propositions As Types Analogy
•
https://oeis.org/wiki/Propositions_As_Types_Analogy
Survey of Precursors Of Category Theory
•
https://inquiryintoinquiry.com/2024/05/24/survey-of-precursors-of-category-…
Regards,
Jon
cc:
https://www.academia.edu/community/5wbQ91
cc:
https://mathstodon.xyz/@Inquiry/112502692087155139